Group Minds and Natural Kinds

Avant, Vol. X, No. 3/2019, doi: 10.26913/avant.2019.03.08
published under license CC BY-NC-ND 3.0

Robert D. Rupert
University of Colorado, Boulder
robert.rupert @ colorado.edu

Published Online First 19 August 2019   Download full text

Abstract: It is often claimed that structured collections of individuals with mental or cognitive states—such collections as courts, countries, and corporations—have mental or cognitive states of their own. The existing critical literature casts substantial doubt on this claim. In this paper, I evaluate a defensive move made by some proponents of the view that groups have mental or cognitive states of their own: to concede that group states and individual states aren’t of the same specific natural kinds, while holding that groups instantiate different species of mental or cognitive states—perhaps a different species of cognition itself—from those instantiated by humans. In order to evaluate this defense of group cognition, I present a view of natural kinds—or at least of the sort of evidence that supports inferences to sameness of natural kind—a view I have previously dubbed the ‘tweak-and-extend’ theory, as well as a theory of cognitive systems. Guided by the tweak-and-extend approach, I arrive at a tentative conclusion: that what is common to models of individual cognitive processing and models of group processing does not suffice to establish sameness of cognitive (or mental) kinds, properties, or state-types across individuals and extant groups, not even at a generic level.

Keywords: cognitive systems; group minds; natural kinds; group cognition; distributed cognition; Christian List; Philip Pettit


References

Anderson, M.L. (2010). Neural reuse: A fundamental organizational principle of the brain. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33 (4), 245–313.

Anderson, M.L. (2014). After Phrenology: Neural Reuse and the Interactive Brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. https://doi.org/10.1162/LEON_r_01169

Arico, A. (2010). Folk psychology, consciousness, and context effects. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1(3), 371–393. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s13164-010-0029-9

Barnier, A.J., Sutton, J., Harris, C.B., & Wilson, R.A. (2008). A conceptual and empirical framework for the social distribution of cognition: The case of memory. Cognitive Systems Research, 9 (1), 33–51. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cogsys.2007.07.002

Block, N. (1978). Troubles with functionalism. In C. Savage (Ed.), Perception and cognition. Issues in the foundations of psychology, Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, vol. 9 (pp. 261–325). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. doi: 10.2307/2215263

Block, N. (1997). Anti-reductionism slaps back. In J. Tomberlin (Ed.), Mind, Causation, World: Philosophical Perspectives 11 (pp. 107–133). Boston: Blackwell. https://doi.org/10.1111/0029-4624.31.s11.5

Botvinick, M.M. & Cohen, J.D. (2014). The computational and neural basis of cognitive control: Charted territory and new frontiers. Cognitive Science 38: 1249–1285. https://doi.org/10.1111/cogs.12126

Brooks, R.A. (1999). Cambrian intelligence: The early history of the new AI. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195333213.001.0001

Chalmers, D. (2008). Foreword to Andy Clark, Supersizing the mind. In A. Clark. Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension (pp. IX–XVI). New York: Oxford University Press.

Churchland, P.M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 78 (2), 67–90. doi: 10.5840/jphil198178268

Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge. MA: MIT Press.

Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. New York: Oxford University Press. doi: https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-1539161

Clark, A. (2011). Finding the mind. Philosophical Studies, 152 (3), 447–461. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-010-9598-9

Clark, A. &  Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58 (1), 7–19. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/58.1.7

Cole, M.W., Reynolds, J.R., Power, J.D., Repovs, G., Anticevic, A., & Braver, T.S. (2013). Multi-task connectivity reveals flexible hubs for adaptive task control. Nature Neuroscience, 16(9), 1348–1355. doi: 10.1038/nn.3470

De Brigard, F. (2017). Cognitive systems and the changing brain. Philosophical Explorations, 20 (2), 224–241. doi: 10.1080/13869795.2017.1312503

Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston, MA: Little, Brown and Company. doi: 10.2307/1422870

Evans, J.St.B.T. & Frankish, K., (Eds.). (2009). In two minds: Dual processes and beyond. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199230167.001.0001

Fodor, J. (1974). Special sciences (Or: The disunity of science as a working hypothesis). Synthese, 28 (2), 97–115. doi: 10.1007/BF00485230

Fodor, J. (1983). The modularity of mind: An essay on faculty psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. doi: 10.1353/lan.1984.0028

Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. doi: 10.2307/1423122

Gendler, T. (2008). Alief and belief. Journal of Philosophy, 105 (10), 634–663. doi: 10.5840/jphil20081051025

Giere, R. (2006). The role of agency in distributed cognitive systems. Philosophy of Science, 73 (5), 710–719. doi: 10.1086/518772

Gilbert, M. (2004). Collective epistemology. Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology, 1 (2), 95–107. https://doi.org/10.3366/epi.2004.1.2.95

Goldstone, R. & Gureckis, T.. (2009). Collective behavior. Topics in Cognitive Science, 1 (3), 412–438. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1756-8765.2009.01038.x

Goldstone, R. & G. Theiner. (2017). The multiple, interacting levels of cognitive systems (MILCS) perspective on group cognition. Philosophical Psychology 30 (3), 338–372. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2017.1295635

Griffiths, T.L., Chater, N., Kemp, C., Perfors, A. & Tenenbaum, J. B. (2010). Probabilistic models of cognition: Exploring representations and inductive biases. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14 (8), 357–364. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2010.05.004

Grush, R. (1997). The architecture of representation. Philosophical Psychology, 10 (1), 5–23. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089708573201

Himmelreich, J. (2015). Review of From Individual to Collective Intentionality: New Essays, Economics and Philosophy, 31 (3), 479–486. doi: 10.1017/s0266267115000218

Huebner, B. (2008). Do you see what we see? An investigation of an argument against collective representation. Philosophical Psychology, 21 (1), 91–112. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515080701870827

Huebner, B. (2013). Macrocognition: A theory of distributed minds and collective intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199926275.001.0001

Huebner, B., Bruno M., & Sarkissian, H. (2010). What does the nation of China think about phenomenal states? Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1 (2), 225–243. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s13164-009-0009-0

Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the Wild. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Kim, J. (1998). Mind in a physical world: An essay on the mind-body problem and mental causation. Cambridge: MIT Press.

Klein, C. (2010). Critical Notice: Cognitive systems and the extended mind by Robert Rupert. The Journal of Mind and Behavior, 31 (3&4), 253–264.

Knobe, J. & Prinz, J. (2008). Intuitions about consciousness: Experimental studies. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 7 (1), 67–83. doi: 10.1007/s11097-007-9066-y

Lewis, D. (1970). How to define theoretical terms. Journal of Philosophy, 67 (13), 427–446. doi: 10.2307/2023861

Lewis, D. (1980). Mad pain and Martian pain. In N. Block (Ed.), Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology, Volume one (pp. 216–222). Cambridge: Harvard University Press. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12162

List, C. (2018). What is it like to be a group agent? Noûs, 52 (2), 295–319.

List, C. & Pettit, P. (2011). Group agency: The possibility, design, and status of corporate agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199591565.001.0001

Marr, D. (1982). Vision: A computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information. Cambridge: MIT Press. doi: 10.7551/mitpress/9780262514620.001.0001

Nolan, D. (1997). Quantitative parsimony. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 48 (3), 329–343. doi: 10.1093/bjps/48.3.329

Putnam, H. (1967) Psychological predicates. In W. H. Capitan and D. D. Merrill (eds.), Art, Mind, and Religion (pp. 37–48). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press. doi: 10.2307/2024154

Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of ‘meaning’. In H. Putnam (ed.), Mind, Language, and Reality: Philosophical Papers, vol. 2 (pp. 215–271). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Roth, A.S. (2014). Indispensability, the discursive dilemma, and groups with minds of their own. In S. R. Chant, F. Hindriks, and G. Preyer (eds.) From Individual to Collective Intentionality: New Essays (pp. 137–162). Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199936502.003.0007

Rovane, C. (2014). Group agency and individualism. Erkenntnis 79 (9): 1663–1684. doi: 10.1007/s10670-014-9634-9

Rumelhart, D.E., Hinton, G.E., & McClelland, J.L. (1986). A general framework for parallel distributed processing. In D.E. Rumelhart, J.L. McClelland, & the PDP Research Group (Eds.), Parallel Distributed Processing: Explorations in the Microstructure of Cognition, Vol. 1, Foundations (pp. 45–76). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Rupert, R.D. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy, 101 (8), 389–428. doi: 10.5840/jphil2004101826

Rupert, R.D. (2005). Minding one’s cognitive systems: When does a group of minds constitute a single cognitive unit? Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology, 1 (3), 177–88. doi: 10.3366/epi.2004.1.3.177

Rupert, R.D. (2009). Cognitive systems and the extended mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195379457.001.0001

Rupert, R.D. (2010). Extended cognition and the priority of cognitive systems. Cognitive Systems Research, 11 (4), 343–56. doi: 10.1016/j.cogsys.2010.04.002

Rupert, R.D. (2011). Empirical arguments for group minds: A critical appraisal. Philosophy Compass, 6 (9), 630–639. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1747-9991.2011.00420.x

Rupert, R.D. (2013). Memory, natural kinds, and cognitive extension; or, Martians don’t remember, and cognitive science is not about cognition. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 4 (1), 25–47. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-012-0129-9

Rupert, R.D. (2014). Against group cognitive states. In S. Chant, F. Hindriks & G. Preyer (Eds.), From individual to collective intentionality (pp. 97–111). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Rupert, R.D. (2018a). The self in the age of cognitive science. Philosophic Exchange, 47 (1). Retrieved May 10, 2019, from https://digitalcommons.brockport.edu/phil_ex/vol47/iss1/2

Rupert, R.D. (2018b). Representation and mental representation. Philosophical Explorations, 21 (2), 204–225. https://doi.org/10.1080/13869795.2018.1477979

Schaffer, J. (2016). Ground rules: Lessons from Wilson. In K. Aizawa and C. Gillett (Eds.), Scientific composition and metaphysical ground (pp. 143–169). London: Palgrave Macmillan.

Schwitzgebel, E. (2015). If materialism is true, the United States is probably conscious. Philosophical Studies, 172 (7), 1697–1721. doi: 10.1007/s11098-014-0387-8

Shoemaker, S. (1981) Some varieties of functionalism. Philosophical Topics, 12 (1), 93–118. doi: 10.5840/philtopics198112145

Sprevak, M. (2009). Extended cognition and functionalism. Journal of Philosophy, 106 (9), 503–27. doi: 10.5840/jphil2009106937

Stich, S. (1996). Deconstructing the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515080802703653

Sytsma, J. & Machery, E. (2009). How to study folk intuitions about phenomenal consciousness. Philosophical Psychology, 22 (1), 21–35.

Sytsma, J. & Machery, E. (2010) Two conceptions of subjective experience. Philosophical Studies, 151, 299–327. doi: 10.1007/s11098-009-9439-x

Theiner, G. & O’Connor, T. (2010). The emergence of group cognition. In A. Corradini and T. O’Connor (Eds.). Emergence in science and philosophy (pp. 78–117). New York: Routledge. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cogsys.2010.07.002

Theiner, G., Allen, C., & Goldstone, R.L. (2010). Recognizing group cognition. Cognitive Systems Research, 11 (4), 378–395.

Tollefsen, D. (2006). From extended mind to collective mind. Cognitive Systems Research, 7 (2–3 ), 140–50. doi: 10.1016/j.cogsys.2006.01.001

Wheeler, M. (2011). In search of clarity about parity. Philosophical Studies, 152 (3), 417–425. doi: 10.1007/s11098-010-9601-5

Wilson, J. (2016). The unity and priority arguments for grounding. In K. Aizawa & C. Gillett (Eds.), Scientific Composition and Metaphysical Ground (pp. 171–204). London: Palgrave Macmillan.

Wilson, M. (2002). Six Views of Embodied Cognition. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 9 (4), 625–36. doi: 10.3758/BF03196322

Wilson, R.A. (2004). Boundaries of the Mind: The Individual in the Fragile Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511606847


“Avant” journal – the task financed under the contract 711/P-DUN/2019 from the funds of the Minister of Science and Higher Education for the dissemination of science.
Czasopismo „Avant” – zadanie finansowane w ramach umowy 711/P-DUN/2019 ze środków Ministra Nauki i Szkolnictwa Wyższego przeznaczonych na działalność upowszechniającą naukę.


Comments are closed.