Avant, Vol. X, No. 2/2019, doi: 10.26913/avant.2019.02.06
published under license CC BY-NC-ND 3.0
Christopher Joseph An
Philosophy Department
Ateneo de Manila University
cjan.phil @ gmail.com
Received 2 July 2018; accepted 13 November 2018; published 11 December 2019. Download full text
Abstract: This paper aims to explore and expand on Wittgenstein’s remarks on the nature of mental imagery. Despite some rather cryptic passages and obvious objections, his notion of mental imagery as possessing a constitutive (and not merely added) element of expressive thought and conceptuality offers critical insights linking perceptual capacities with our shared practices. In particular I seek to further develop Wittgenstein’s claim that perceptual impressions presuppose a “mastery of a technique.” I argue that this sense of technique, understood as acquired conceptual capacities, can explain and capture the rich and varied spectrum of expressive visual content that can be accessed by human beings initiated and embedded in a variety of shared practices. Using Gilbert Ryle’s account of dispositions, I cash out the notion of acquired conceptual capacities as spanning a wide latitude of responsive dispositions from mere “blind” visual habits to more normatively-guided, intelligent, and deliberately-trained visual “skills.” Visual impressions construed as such are hardly perceptually (nor representationally) univocal and instead exhibit a dynamic and reflexive plurivocity manifested through one’s initiation into shared practices and forms of life. This plurivocity makes possible a rich array of visual affordances that would otherwise not be accessible outside the context of a shared practice. This suggests that human beings possess a distinctive kind of expressive and responsive intelligence which picks out visual affordances determined not so much by a merely receptive perceptual faculty but by the subject’s skillful, active, and responsive engagement with the world.
Keywords: Wittgenstein; mental imagery; conceptual capacities; visual affordances; acquired dispositions
References
Bennett, M.R. and Hacker, P.M.S. (2003). Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience. Oxford: Blackwell. | ||||
Dewey, J. (1896). The reflex arc concept in psychology. Psychological Review, 3/4, 357-70. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0070405 |
||||
Gibson, J.J. (1979/1986). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. | ||||
McDowell, J. (1996). Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. https://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctvjghtzj |
||||
McGinn, M. (1997/2013). Wittgenstein and the Philosophical Investigations. London: Routledge. | ||||
Noë, A. (2012). Varieties of Presence. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. https://doi.org/10.4159/harvard.9780674063013 |
||||
Nyíri, K. (2017). Pictorial Truth: Essays on Wittgenstein, Realism, and Conservatism. Dunabogdány. | ||||
Rietveld, E. and Kiverstein, J. (2014). A rich landscape of affordances. Ecological Psychology, 26/4, 325-52. https://doi.org/10.1080/10407413.2014.958035 |
||||
Ryle, G. (1949/2009). The Concept of Mind. Oxford: Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9780203875858 |
||||
Sellars, W. (1956/1963). Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. In W. Sellars, Science, Perception, and Reality. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. | ||||
Wittgenstein, L. (1963). Philosophical Investigations. (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell (PI). | ||||
Wittgenstein, L. (1967). Philosophical Grammar. (R. Rhees Ed., A. Kenny, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell (PG). | ||||
Wittgenstein, L. (1980). Culture and Value. (G.H. von Wright in collaboration with H. Nyman Eds., P. Winch Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell (CV). |